Sunday 28 April 2013

The Social Contract (talk given to Kingston Philosophy Cafe 2nd April 2013)



The Social Contract

The idea of the Social Contract is as old as philosophy itself.   It can be summarised as the idea that the state is the result of a contract between its citizens, who realise that though living under the rule of law may not be in their short term interest, as it restricts and controls them, it is very much in their long term interest and so they decide to sacrifice short term interest for long term gain and contrive to create rule of law, the state.    We can imagine a “state of nature” in which there is no rule of law, prior to the social contract, and the post-contract political society we actually live in.   Notice that this means that the state we all live in is an artificial one, against nature.

That’s all there is to it really.    The theory was considered and rejected in classical times and it is only in the sixteenth century with the beginning of the modern era that it comes back into fashion, and indeed becomes entirely dominant in political theory.    First Hobbes, then Locke, Rousseau, Kant, and then John Rawls, whose theory of Justice is considered by many the most important work of political theory of the twentieth century, all use the metaphor of the social contract in some way and it is hard to find any criticism of it.   Politicians and ordinary people who have never heard of the political theory also talk freely of our “contract with society” and in other ways that show that they too endorse the notion that we have an implied contract with each other that ought to govern or at least influence our behaviour.

The first problem with the theory is an empirical one.   There is not the slightest evidence that a state or proto-state has ever been founded by a contract between its citizens.    History teaches us that really without exception states are founded by acts of war, which seem to be the very opposite of contracts.     We can also ask ourselves at an individual level, how do we come by our nationality, our membership of and allegiance to a state?    The answer is by birth.    There is no act of consent and we have absolutely no choice in the matter.    We are citizens of a state just by being born, by simply existing, and choice, consent, or contract never, ever come in to play.

So I’m not going to talk about finer points of social contract theory, because there’s no point, it’s not true, and as philosophers we are only interested in truth .    The interesting question is how come the great minds of modern political theory, philosophers of the stature of Hobbes or Kant, come to believe almost universally and without question in a theory which is so evidently untrue?   Are they perhaps under the influence of some illusion, some ideology that prevents them from seeing the truth?    You bet they are.    It’s called the Enlightenment, and there are two aspects of it I want to look at tonight which are Individualism and Rationalism,  two sides of the same coin really which always go together, but which I think it will be useful to distinguish here.   They are views about the nature of the Absolute, the ground of truth, and they hold that the individual, and his reason, are the absolute standard against which everything must be assessed.

Individualism.

The Enlightenment holds that the “man is the measure of all things”, which is a statement about the nature of the Absolute.   Many modern philosophers will say that they no longer believe in “Absolutes” which they see as old-fashioned and archaic and inappropriate in our pluralistic age, but if they hold that man is the measure of all things, indisputably they do believe in an absolute.   In any case you can’t do philosophy if you reject the notion of absolute truth.   If truth is not absolute, but only relative, then as well as being relatively true it is also relatively untrue, and you can’t have a truth that is untrue, so rejection of the Absolute is rejection of philosophy itself.   Now, if man, the individual, is the absolute, then it follows that all cultural life is his creation and is relative to him, the result of his efforts.     From this it follows that if the state exists it too must be a result of something done by the individual, so individuals must at some time have realised the benefits of living in a political community and contrived to create it through some kind of contract.  In other words the idea of the contract is a result of the premise that man is the measure of all things, which is an aspiration of the enlightenment, and not a result of observation of reality at all.

So what about that aspiration?    It seems fine and unobjectionable really, doesn’t it?    But the thinking that gave rise to it grew out of the development of science, and it’s reasonable to apply scientific method to it.    We can say that the hypothesis of individualism (more strictly atomism, but I’m going to stick with the broader term individualism tonight) predicts that the state must be the result of agreement between its citizens, and we can see if the evidence supports it or not.   We have already seen that it doesn’t, so the hypothesis must be wrong.    But if this means that the individual is not the absolute what then is?     We are so used to thinking of ourselves as independent individuals, the building blocks of society, that it can be hard to imagine an alternative view, but one was given by Aristotle, who said for example that “man is by nature a political animal” and “it is clear the state is both natural and prior to the individual.

Aristotle would not say such things if he wasn’t aware of an opposite view (i.e. that the state is artificial and subsequent to the individual) , and we can take his comments to be criticism of some kind of social contract theory.   By saying that man is by nature a political animal,  he implies that there is no state of nature, in which we might exist as some kind of “noble savage”, and this means that the way we live is not artificial, as it is for the contractarians, but normal and natural, something that I personally feel more comfortable with.    And by saying that the state is prior to the individual he gives a clear alternative to individualism which says that actually the state comes first, the individual second.    This might seem counterintuitive, but it points to a fundamental problem with contract theory, which is this:    how can you make contracts, if you don’t first have rule of law?    Contracts are in general about exchange, and to have exchange you must first have private property, and if you have private property you must have a state which guarantees and protects it (that’s the difference between property and mere possession), so it makes no sense to say that you contract to create the state because it must have existed in the first place so that you could make a contract.   The very thing you are trying to explain by the social contract is presupposed.    And it is not just a circular argument, which would be defective but not necessarily false.   It’s worse than that, it's back to front.   It says that the individual is the cause of the state but actually the state is the cause of the individual.    The individual is not the same as the particular, the “specimen of humanity”, and properly understood the individual is both particular and universal united, and a very important aspect of individuality is the rights conferred (universally) on particular people by the state such as the right to own property, to be protected from assault, physical abuse and so on.

So individualism, the belief that the individual is the absolute or that man is the measure of all things, while it may seem natural to us, is problematic and there is an alternative expressed in classical philosophy which sees the individual as created by the state, not vice versa.    So here’s a question for discussion.     Is there such thing as society?    If you are an individualist the answer has to be yes, because the individual is absolute and anything else cultural that exists must be made up of relations between individuals, because there is nothing else, and these relations are what we mean when we speak of society.    But what is society actually?     Can you point to it?   Does it exist at all?    For my part I’d say no, it doesn’t,  it’s just an abstraction, and whenever I hear someone using the word society or social (as in “social contract” or “social relation”) or, worst of all,  “intersubjective”, it puts me on my guard because I know I am dealing with an individualist and that I am not going to  agree with them.    What do you think?

Rationalism

Now, moving on to rationalism, well, you can say that there is an obvious problem with individualism which is that there are seven billion or so of us on the planet, and we are all different, so that’s seven billion absolutes and clearly that is not much use.   But enlightenment gets round this by saying that it is one aspect only of the individual that is absolute which is his reason, which is the same for everyone and common to all (this is why strictly it is atomism rather than individualism).    So let’s have a quick look at this idea that it is Reason that is the Absolute.    After all this seems like something it would be unreasonable to disagree with, because if reason doesn’t ground knowledge, what is left?    It seems irrational to disagree with this, and like going back to more primitive, prescientific, superstitious times. 

There is actually a reasonable objection to the notion that reason is the absolute, the yardstick against which everything should be measured and assessed, and you can find it in ancient political theory in the concept of the four cardinal virtues (wisdom, courage, discipline, and justice).    Now, why are there four cardinal virtues?    Why not three or five, or twenty seven?    The reason is that everything that exists, at least according to Aristotle, must have four causes:   material, efficient, formal and final;   and these are essential to its existence, which means that if any one is missing the thing can’t exist, or, turning that round, if it does exist then it follows that each of the four causes must also exist.    The four causes are all-encompassing, nothing else is needed so they are also sufficient.   In the case of philosophy, the thing we want most to know is the nature of the good.    Now the good exists.    This is a proposition modern philosophy has trouble with, but intuitively we all know it to be true, so it follows that it must have material efficient formal and final causes.    These are the cardinal virtues.     Material cause is wisdom, because knowledge is the stuff of which the good is made, and if there were no knowledge clearly also there would be no good.      Efficient cause is courage, because that is the energy that makes the good happen and without that energy, that willingness to risk life for the sake of the good, it couldn’t exist.    Formal cause is reason and its virtue of control, discipline, temperance, whatever you want to call it, because the good isn’t just an abstract notion, it has shape, and the shape or form is given to it by restraint and control.    The final cause is Justice, which is the purpose, the telos or end of the good, and without this too the good couldn’t exist, because there wouldn’t be any point.    The virtues are cardinal because they stand on their own, they are quite different things and cannot be expressed in terms of each other.

Now let’s take a look at what Enlightenment does with this.    There is no direct Enlightenment criticism of the notion of the four cardinal virtues and it is hard to see how there could be because you can’t be an Enlightenment philosopher if you understand them, and in practice the Enlightement isn’t built on a criticism of classical philosophy, but on ignoring it and starting again from scratch;   but there is clear implied criticism of it in the notion of the social contract.

Let’s start with the notion of Justice, the concept political theory most wants to understand.     According to social contract theory, Justice is a result of reason.   This means that justice is no longer a cardinal virtue, because you can’t be a cardinal virtue if you are the result of something else, you are relative to and subordinate to that thing.     Justice becomes a part of reason, and you are now down to three cardinal virtues.    In some cases, Rawls being the best example, Justice isn’t just subordinated to reason.   It actually disappears.    Rawls’ book is based on the notion that “justice is fairness”.    If this is correct, then you no longer need the word justice at all because you can replace it in every instance with the word “fairness” and “justice” simply disappears.    It isn’t correct, because fairness and justice are quite different concepts.    Modern philosophers have a habit of using the term “justice” as a high-falutin’ term for moral rectitude, or just fairness, but actually that is not what it means.   If you doubt this, just pick up a tabloid newspaper.   They are always calling for justice, and when they do what they mean is that they want someone to suffer.   They are calling for blood, for vengeance, for something do be done by the state to someone they think has transgressed.   You can’t “do” fairness which is just a passive standard, and the fact of vengeance is enough to see that justice and fairness  or moral rectitude aren’t the same thing.    Rawls’ book is called “A Theory of Justice” but actually it is nothing of the sort, it is just a theory of fairness.   Rawls has done that classic thing which as Daniel Kahneman points out in Thinking Fast, Thinking Slow we all do when faced with a difficult question, which is to substitute an easier one.    "What is Justice?" is certainly a difficult question, so it comes naturally to us to substitute an easier one, "what is fairness" and this is just what Rawls has done.    His answer can be expressed in four words, a simple rule of the playground for fair division:   you half, I choose.    And we can ask, who knows more about justice, us, or John Rawls?    You might think the answer is John Rawls, who is after all considered the leading 20th century authority on the subject.   But actually, he is not aware of the substitution he has made, and if we are aware of the that and understand that justice is not the same as fairness, we can say we know more than him because we at least know one thing about justice, whereas Rawls knows precisely nothing, because all his thinking and writing on the matter is actually about another subject.

Now what about courage?    Courage is the efficient cause of the state, because before you can have any kind of government, you first have to control a territory in which you can enforce the rule of law, and this means you have to have armed forces, people who are willing to risk their lives in order to establish and maintain the rule of law.   Power is the essence of politics.   If you don’t have power, it’s not politics and politics cannot exist without power, without the instruments of repression and control, the armed forces, the penal system, the courts and so on.   Without courage, the state and the rule of law could not exist, that is how important it is.   In a word, it is essential, and you can’t get any more important than that.

So let’s have a look at how Social Contract theorists think about power.    At the modern and weakest extreme, thinkers like John Rawls ignore power altogether, and there is no mention of it at all in Rawls’  A Theory of Justice, which is another reason you can say it is not a work of political theory, because you can’t have a political theory that leaves out the most important aspect of the political, power.    Less wooly thinkers like Hobbes on the other hand do clearly understand the importance of political power, because for Hobbes “a covenant without the sword is of no force to bind a man”.    This is fairly typical of contractarian thinking.   In an ideal world where everyone was rational and negated their personal interests in favour of the general, so the thinking goes, you wouldn’t need power, or government at all really;  but that is a utopia we will never reach because people cannot be trusted to behave rationally all the time without some external encouragement, so power is an unfortunate necessity.    It’s there, but subordinate to reason and resulting from reason, and as to where it comes from, well this isn’t really addressed but the implication is that the people who put their lives on the line to create that power are just the hired help, and they do it because they are paid to.    This really isn’t good enough – would you risk your life in return for wages?    It doesn’t make sense.   And there is a logical fallacy here.   Just because you identify a “need” for something doesn’t mean that that thing exists or that that need is satisfied.    I need a helicopter and a yacht, but unfortunately that doesn’t mean that I have them.

Whatever way you look at it the virtue of courage has gone.   In Rawles it is totally absent, and in Hobbes, Rouseau and the rest, it is subordinate to reason, resulting from it, and therefore is no longer a cardinal virtue.   So in modern contractarian thinking both the efficient cause of the good, Courage, and it’s final cause, Justice, have either disappeared altogether, or have been so effectively subordinated to Reason that they no longer function as cardinal virtues.      So  can you see what has this means?    What is a philosophy like that has abandoned efficient and final cause?    Well the final cause is purpose, telos, so you can say that without this, philosophy has no purpose, and because purpose is also meaning you can say with some accuracy that this philosophy has become meaningless.   And efficient cause is power, so a philosophy that lacks efficient cause is impotent;  so modern contractarian thinking is pointless, meaningless, and impotent;   and that is in fact the general perception of modern philosophy, not just as seen from the outside but also the view of many of its practitioners most of whom have long abandoned the idea that philosophy has any purpose beyond academic exercise.  

So if you like the idea of philosophy that is pointless and impotent, modern philosophy with its contractarian views is for you.    If you think on the other hand that it ought to have a purpose, a meaning, and power, then you need to reject the notion that Reason is the absolute, that man is the measure of all things, and say instead that the Absolute is the Good, and that it has four pillars in the cardinal virtues which must be part of any political theory.    Reason is indeed one of them, but you need the rest as well.    And by the way there is a view these days that political theory is a kind of special interest in philosophy;   but if political theory is an account of justice, and justice is what gives meaning to the good, it’s pretty clear that it is essential and perhaps the most important  aspect of philosophy of all.     It’s a real problem then that the big hitters in modern philosophy all adopt the notion of the social contract, because it means their ideas are worthless and we really need to start all over again if we want to understand the political.   There is one philosopher in the modern era, and to my knowledge only one, who does try to build an account of the state that includes the cardinal virtues, and who rejects the notion of social contract out of hand, and that is Hegel in the Philosophy of Right.    There’s nothing else apart from the ancient classics, so I guess that is where you have to start.